ABSTRACT universal User Manual Page 29

  • Download
  • Add to my manuals
  • Print
  • Page
    / 39
  • Table of contents
  • BOOKMARKS
  • Rated. / 5. Based on customer reviews
Page view 28
as ontological holism or monism). However, if we dig a little deeper, we will
find a way to connect Hegel’s position as I have outlined it to the thinking of
some of the British Idealists, and to see that the questions an d issues that drew
them to the doctrine of the concrete universal in this properly Hegelian form
are not as alien to us as may have appeared hitherto.
Where a doctrine of the concrete universal emerges that is close to the one I
have attributed to Hegel, is in the way that some of the British Idealists sought
to attack empiricist claims concerning ‘the abstractness of thought’. This
issue, which was of widespread concern, has several different aspects. The first
is epistemological: thought has only a subordinate role to play in knowledge,
because our primary engagement with the world comes directly through the
senses, from which thought abstracts. The second is psychological: the
general ideas through which we think about the world are generated via a
process of abstraction from the simple ideas we acquire through sensible
experience. The third is logic al: logical thought involves ever more
abstraction, as we move away from the content of our experience into higher
and higher levels of generality. And the fourth might be termed ‘existential’:
thought leads us into a realm of unreal abstractions, away from the concrete
reality of lived experience and an immediate grasp of things in their unique
individuality. To many of the Idealists, this conception of the abstractness of
thought was mistaken; to quote a summary of their positi on: ‘[T]hought is
essentially a process of concretion, not a process of abstraction from an
experience which , as given, is already concrete’.
66
As we shall show, it is when
addressing this issue that a number of the British Idealists
67
come closest to
adopting the Hegelian doc trine of the concrete universal as characterized
above, and in a way that shows that doctrine to have contemporary interest.
We can see most clearly how the attack on the thesis that thought involves
abstraction enabled a properly Hegelian doctrine of the concrete universal to
emerge by looking in some detail at one of the first British Idealists to launch
such an attack, namely T. H. Green. Green outlines the abstractionist picture
of thought, with its various problematic dimensions, as follows:
Give sensation this first inch, and it takes an ell. If sense gives a knowledge of
properties, nothing remains for thought but to abstract and combine them,
and it is vain then to re-assert for the data of thought, for its abstractions and
‘mixed modes,’ the dignity of the ‘things themselves.’ Thought has abdicated
66
George H. Sabine, ‘The Concreteness of Thought’, Philosophical Review, 16 (1907) No. 2:
154–69, esp. p. 154.
67
The question of whether Bradley is an exception here is too complex to be dealt with properly
in what follows: for on the one hand, while Bradley may seem to be more insistent than other
Idealist writers on the abstractive nature of thought, and thus more pessimistic about its
capacity to grasp the unique individuality of reality, he nonetheless also seems to have shared
their view that thought is required in order to give experience a particular content, where this
once again relies on a non-abstractionist account of our concepts. For an enlightening
discussion of these issues, see Phillip Ferreira, Bradley and the Structure of Knowledge (Albany,
1999), where 41–4 are particularly relevant to the themes of this paper.
HEGEL AND THE CONCRETE UNIVERSAL 143
Page view 28
1 2 ... 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 ... 38 39

Comments to this Manuals

No comments