ABSTRACT universal User Manual Page 9

  • Download
  • Add to my manuals
  • Print
  • Page
    / 39
  • Table of contents
  • BOOKMARKS
  • Rated. / 5. Based on customer reviews
Page view 8
This conception of the concrete universal has the advantage that it avoids the
peculiar conflation of individuality with universality that we saw earlier,
universal of an abstraction from the particular and different, but the unity which is
immanent in them and finds in them its own necessary expression; not an arbitrary
invention of the observing and classifying mind unifying in its own imagination things
which are yet essentially different, but an idea which expresses the inner dialectic, the
movement or process towards unity, which exists in and constitutes the being of the
objects themselves. This deeper and truer universality is that which may be designated
ideal or organic universality.
(John Caird, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
(Glasgow, 1904) 217–18)
Cf. also Bosanquet, The Principle of Individuality and Value, 37:
A world or cosmos is a system of members, such that every member, being ex hypothesi
distinct, nevertheless contributes to the unity of the whole in virtue of the peculiarities
which constitute its distinctness. And the important point for us at present is the
difference of principle between a world and a class. It takes all sorts to make a world; a
class is essentially of one sort only. In a word, the difference is that the ultimate principle
of unity and community is fully exemplified in the former, but only superficially in the
latter. The ultimate principle, we may say, is sameness in the other; generality is sameness
in spite of the other; universality is sameness by means of the other.
Similar comments include Bernard Bosanquet, ‘Life and Philosophy’, in Contemporary British
Philosophy, edited by J. H. Muirhead, first series (London, 1924) 51–74, esp. p. 62: ‘The universal,
the very life and spirit of logic, did not mean [to me] a general predicate, but the plastic unity of an
inclusive system’; and Bernard Bosanquet, The Distinction Between Mind and its Objects
(Manchester, 1913) 34: ‘a universal is a working connection within particulars’. Cf. also Richard
Lewis Nettleship, Philosophical Remains of Richard Lewis Nettleship, edited by A. C. Bradley, 2nd
edn (London, 1901) 158–9:
The universal is said to contain or include its particulars. This, of course, is a spatial
metaphor, and we always have to guard against the influence of spatial associations.
But the metaphor helps some minds to realize the truth, and it is convenient as bringing
out the fact that particulars, while excluding one another, also make up, or are included
in, one whole. To say, for example, that humanity includes all men may help one to
realize the truth that, though men exclude one another, they still form a unity.
and R. G. Collingwood, Speculum Mentis (Oxford, 1924) 220–1:
This absolute whole is the concrete universal; for concrete universality is indivi-
duality, the individual being simply the unity of the universal and the particular.
The absolute individual is universal in that it is what it is throughout, and every part
of it is as individual as itself. On the other hand it is no mere abstraction, the abstract
quality of individualness, but an individual which includes all others. It is the system
of systems, the world of worlds.
This view of the concrete universal persists in the thinking of later generations of British writers
on Hegel, such as T. M. Knox: see, e.g. his translator’s notes to his translation of Hegel’s
Philosophy of Right (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1952) 323–4 [my emphasis]:
An abstract universal has no organic connexion with its particulars. Mind, or reason,
as a concrete universal, particularizes itself into differences which are interconnected by
its universality in the same way in which parts of the organism are held together by the
single life which all things share. The parts depend on the whole for their life, but on
the other hand the persistence of life necessitates the differentiation of the part.
Cf. also T. L. S. Sprigge, ‘Bradley’ in Routledge History of Philosophy VII: The Nineteenth
Century, edited by C. L. Ten (London, 1994) 437–58, esp. p. 440: ‘[P]roponents of the concrete
universal usually take the totality of its instances as itself the universal in question, arguing that
it is a kind of whole which is present in each of its parts’.
HEGEL AND THE CONCRETE UNIVERSAL 123
Page view 8
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 ... 38 39

Comments to this Manuals

No comments